The purpose of this blog
is to explore religious doubts.
Experience
suggests that people have a number of ways of dealing with religious
doubts. The more high-brow read up on
apologetics to look for arguments that will rationally squelch them. The more squeamish may sweep them under the
rug and pretend they are not there. Others
try to drown their doubts in raw emotions at revivals. Finally, some resort to anti-intellectualism and
so regard thought itself as an occasion for sin.
All these very different ways of
handling doubts have one thing in common: none of them look at the doubts themselves
very closely. What would we learn if we
looked at the doubts themselves? This
blog will explore the different types of doubts which have been brought to my
attention by fellow believers, so that others may learn how to deal with their
own doubts.
Doubts
are so troublesome because people tend to regard all of them as some kind of
moral defect. We will examine some
doubts that qualify as defects, but there are other kinds of doubts. It is not enough to say that doubts form a
class, though. We must also see them
against their proper backdrop—certitude.
We first affirm (with Thomas Aquinas)
that the intellect seeks truth.1
When the intellect is assured of its possession of truth, says John Rickaby, it experiences
certitude.2 The mind with
certitude assents to something for reasons which do not allow any “solid,
reasonable misgivings.”3 How
does certitude work?
One example is the distance of my home
from work. I have used the odometer to
find the distance. I have measured the
distance more than once. I have no
“solid or reasonable misgivings” about the odometer itself; the readings are
consistent. I am sure that if I used any
number of other cars, the distance would be the same. In short, I enjoy the assured possession of
the truth that my home is a certain number of miles from work.
Another example is taken from what used
to be called the Laws of Thought. One of
these is the Principle of Contradiction, which Richard F. Clarke, S.J. defines
as “nothing can at the same time exist and not exist.”4 Why do I enjoy certitude about this
principle? One reason is because there
is no way to corroborate simultaneous existence and non-existence.
To illustrate, suppose I have one cat,
and I see it go into the laundry room, which conveniently has no exit. I can verify that the cat is there by seeing
it. Again, if I have one cat and I see
it leave the laundry room, I can go in there and verify that the cat is no
longer there. So far, so good.
But if I am told by someone that the cat
is in the laundry room and is not in the laundry room, how can I assure myself
that the cat is there and is not there at the same time? Not only can I not imagine the violation of
the Principle of Contradiction, but I also cannot imagine a way to prove its
violation without resorting to underhanded, verbal tricks. Therefore, I have perfect confidence in the
Principle of Contradiction.
(What about people who do violate the
Principle of Contradiction? Either they
must think that “truth and falsity are mere words”5 or they must be mentally
unsound.)
Now, as Rickaby notes, we do not know
all things with this kind of certitude. But
certitude is the ideal. My certitude in
a few things makes it possible for me to gauge how far a great many other facts
and ideas are from the truth. Certitude
is also the internal sign that our intellect has attained to some truth; it is
the warrant that authorizes us either to act or to acquire more truths in its
train.
Our next step is to discuss those states
of mind which fall short of certitude, which will bring us to doubt.
END NOTES
1.
Aquinas Summa Theologiae I, Q. 16, Art. 1.
2.
John Rickaby, The First Principles of Knowledge, 4th
ed. (London: Longmans, Green & Co.,
1901), p. 42.
3.
Ibid.
4.
Richard F. Clarke, Logic, 4th ed. (London: Longmans, Green & Co., 1897), p. 33.
5.
Ibid., p. 34.
No comments:
Post a Comment